$2.10$ Completeness of $\mathbb{R}$ By Theorem $2.7 .9$, between any two real numbers, points on the number line, there exists a rational number. This suggests there are a lot of rational numbers, but it is not clear from this Theorem whether the entire real line consists of only rational numbers. Some people might wish this were the case because then each real number could be described, not just as a point on a line but also algebraically, as the quotient of integers. Before 500 B.C., a group of mathematicians, led by Pythagoras believed in this, but they discovered their beliefs were false. It happened roughly like this. They knew they could construct the square root of two as the diagonal of a right triangle in which the two sides have unit length; thus they could regard $\sqrt{2}$ as a number. Unfortunately, they were also sble to show $\sqrt{2}$ could not be written as the quotient of two integers. This discovery that the rational numbers could not even account for the results of geometric constructions was very upsetting to the Pythagoreans, especially when it became clear there were an endless supply of such “irrational” numbers. This shows that if it is desired to consider all points on the number line, it is necessary to abandon the attempt to describe arbitrary real numbers in a purely algebraic manner using only the integers. Some might desire to throw out all the irrational numbers, and considering only the rational numbers, confine their attention to algebra, but this is not the approsch to be followed here because it will effectively eliminate every major theorem of calculus and analysis. In this book real numbers will continue to be the points on the number line, a line which has no holes. This lack of holes is more precisely described in the following way. Definition 2.10.1 A non empty set, $S \subseteq \mathbb{R}$ is bounded above (below) if there exists $x \in \mathbb{R}$ such that $x \geq(\leq) s$ for all $s \in S$. If $S$ is a nonempty set in $\mathbb{R}$ which is bounded above, then a number, l which has the property that l is an upper bound and that every other upper bound is no smaller than $l$ is called a least upper bound, l.u.b. (S) or often sup $(S)$. If $S$ is a nonempty set bounded below, define the greatest lower bound, g.l.b. $(S)$ or $\inf (S)$ similarly. Thus $g$ is the g.l.b. $(S)$ means $g$ is a lower bound for $S$ and it is the largest of all lower bounds. If $S$ is a nonempty subset of $\mathbb{R}$ which is not bounded above, this information is expressed by saying sup $(S)=+\infty$ and if $S$ is not bounded below, $\inf (S)=-\infty$. In an appendix, there is a proof that the real numers can be obtained as equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rational numbers but in this book, we follow the historical development of the subject and accept it as an axiom. In other words, we will believe in the real numbers and this axiom. The completeness axiom was identified by Bolzano as the reason for the truth of the intermediate value theorem for continuous functions around 1818. However, every existence theorem in calculus depends on some form of the completeness axiom. Axiom 2.10.2 (completeness) Every nonempty set of real numbers which is bounded above has a least upper bound and every nonempty set of real numbers which is bounded below has a greatest lower bound. It is this axiom which distinguishes Calculus from Algebra. A fundamental result shout sup and inf is the following. Proposition 2.10.3 Let $S$ be a nonempty set and suppose sup $(S)$ exists. Then for every $\delta>0$, $$ S \cap(\sup (S)-\delta, \sup (S)] \neq \emptyset $$ If $\inf (S)$ exists, then for every $\delta>0$, $$ S \cap[\inf (S), \inf (S)+\delta) \neq \varphi . $$ |
real analysis代写analysis 2, analysis 3请认准UprivateTA™. UprivateTA™为您的留学生涯保驾护航。
代写
隐藏