Proof: Consider the first claim. If the indicated set equals $\emptyset$, then sup $(S)-\delta$ is an upper bound for $S$ which is smaller than sup $(S)$, contrary to the definition of $\sup (S)$ as the least upper bound. In the second claim, if the indicated set equals $\emptyset$, then inf $(S)+\delta$ would be a lower bound which is larger than inf $(S)$ contrary to the definition of inf $(S)$. The wonderful thing about sup is that you can switch the order in which they occur. The same thing holds for inf. It is also convenient to generalize the notion of sup and inf so that we don’t have to worry about whether it is a real number. Definition 2.10.4 Let $f(a, b) \in[-\infty, \infty]$ for $a \in A$ and $b \in B$ where $A, B$ are nonempty sets which means that $f(a, b)$ is either a number, $\infty$, or $-\infty$. The symbol, $+\infty$ is interpreted as a point out at the end of the number line which is larger than every real number. Of course there is no such number. That is why it is called $\infty$. The symbol, $-\infty$ is interpreted similarly. Then sup $_{a \in A} f(a, b)$ means sup $\left(S_{b}\right)$ where $S_{b} \equiv{f(a, b): a \in A}$. A similar convention holds for inf. Unlike limits, you can take the sup in different orders, same for inf. Lemma 2.10.5 Let $f(a, b) \in[-\infty, \infty]$ for $a \in A$ and $b \in B$ where $A, B$ are sets. Then $$ \sup {a \in A} \sup {b \in B} f(a, b)=\sup {b \in B} \sup {a \in A} f(a, b) . $$ Also, you can replace sup with inf. Proof: Note that for all $a, b, f(a, b) \leq \sup {b \in B} \sup {a \in A} f(a, b)$ and therefore, for all $a, \sup {b \in B} f(a, b) \leq \sup {b \in B} \sup {a \in A} f(a, b)$. Therefore, $$ \sup {a \in A} \sup {b \in B} f(a, b) \leq \sup {b \in B} a \in A \atop f(a, b) . $$ Repeat the same argument interchanging $a$ and $b$, to get the conclusion of the lemms. Similar considerations give the same result for inf. $2.11$ Existence of Roots What is $\sqrt[5]{7}$ and does it even exist? You can ask for it on your calculator and the calculator will give you a number which multiplied by itself 5 times will yield a number which is close to 7 but it isn’t exactly right. Why should there exist a number which works exactly? Every one you find, appears to be some sort of approximation at best. If you can’t produce one, why should you believe it is even there? The following is an argument that roots exist. You fill in the details of the argument. Brsically, roots exist in anslysis because of completeness of the real line. Here is a lemms. Lemma 2.11.1 Suppose $n \in \mathbb{N}$ and $a>0$. Then if $x^{n}-a \neq 0$, there exists $\delta>0$ such that whenever $$ y \in(x-\delta, x+\delta) $$ it follows $y^{n}-a \neq 0$ and has the same sign as $x^{n}-a$. Proof: Using the binomial theorem, $y^{n}=(y-x+x)^{n}$ $$ =\sum_{k=0}^{n-1}\left(\begin{array}{c} n \ k \end{array}\right)(y-x)^{n-k} x^{k}+x^{n} $$ Let $|y-x|<1$. Then using the triangle inequality, it follows that for $|y-x|<1$, $$ \left|y^{n}-x^{n}\right| \leq|y-x| \sum_{k=0}^{n-1}\left(\begin{array}{c} n \ k \end{array}\right)|x|^{k} \equiv C|x-y| $$ |
real analysis代写analysis 2, analysis 3请认准UprivateTA™. UprivateTA™为您的留学生涯保驾护航。
代写
隐藏